IUS ET VERITAS 63
15
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
https://doi.org/10.18800/iusetveritas.202102.001
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative
framework for extraterritorial self-defense against Non-
State Actors(*)(**)
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la
legítima defensa extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Moisés Montiel Mogollón(***)
Universidad Iberoamericana (Ciudad de México, México)
Abstract: The UN Charter law governing self-defense is inadequate to address emerging
modalities of armed violence caused by non-State actors located in the territory of
non-consenting third States. This paper o󰀨ers an alternative grounded in the state of
necessity as a circumstance excluding wrongfulness as per the law of State responsibility.
The contention is that in integrating the rationale behind necessity as an excuse for
non-performance of obligations and the conditions and processes under article 51 of
the UN Charter, the law allows for an exercise of extraterritorial self-defense against
non-State actors which safeguards the territorial State’s sovereignty and the need for a
legal alternative of defense for the defending State without toeing the line of aggression.
Keywords: Self-Defense - Non-state Actors - State responsibility - State of Necessity
- United Nations Security Council
Resumen: El régimen de la Carta de la ONU que tutela la legítima defensa es
inadecuado para lidiar con las modalidades emergentes de violencia armada causada
por actores no estatales situados en el territorio de un tercer Estado que no consiente
a intervención. Este artículo ofrece una alternativa basada en el estado de necesidad
como excluyente de la ilicitud de acuerdo con el régimen de la Responsabilidad
Internacional del Estado. La proposición es que, al integrar el razonamiento que soporta
a la necesidad como excusa para el incumplimiento de obligaciones y las condiciones
y procesos existentes en el marco del artículo 51 de la Carta de la ONU, el derecho
internacional permite el ejercicio de legítima defensa extraterritorial contra actores no
estatales que salvaguarda la soberanía del Estado territorial y la necesidad de una
alternativa legal de defensa para el Estado atacado sin cruzar la línea de la agresión.
Palabras clave: Legítima Defensa - Actores no Estatales - Responsabilidad Internacional
del Estado - Estado de Necesidad - Consejo de Seguridad de las Naciones Unidas
(*) Editorial Team note: This article was received on September 2, 2021 and its publication was approved on November 28, 2021.
(**) The author wishes to thank Santiago Vargas Niño and Alonso Gurmendi for their invaluable input in putting this piece together in
record time, and also Ana Soa Vargas for assisting in the research and, in general, for her unlimited patience. Views and mistakes
are the authors own.
(***) LL.B. (Universidad Central de Venezuela), LL.M. (Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy, Tufts University). Adjunct Professor of Treaty
Law (Universidad Iberoamericana, Mexico) and Law of Armed Conict (Universidad Panamericana, Mexico). Managing Partner at
Lotus Soluciones Legales (Mexico City, Mexico). ORCID: https://orcid.org/0000-0002-9042-4098. Email address: mmontiel@up.edu.
mx.
16 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
1. Introduction
To the best of current knowledge (Haque, 2021) (Modirzadeh,
2021) there is no normative enshrinement of the right self-
defense against non-State actors operating from the territory
of a third-State without the need for consent of the territorial
State (Paddeu, 2020)(1) that is generally accepted or free from
contestation. As last February’s Security Council Arria-formula
meeting(2) made evident, the articulations of normativity are not
enough in number or magnitude to show a customary extension
of the right enshrined in article 51 of the UN Charter (Montiel,
2021), and State practice is far from general or consistent. The
general position of States on this contention was aptly identied
by prof. Modirzadeh as one of silence (Modirzadeh, 2021). The
result of this is that the Charter law governing self-defense
must be held to operate only among States for the time being.
Seeing as the joint reading of articles 2(4) and 51 of the UN
Charter counterintuitively restrict self-defense to inter-State
exchanges, and despite some ambiguous language by the
UNSC on the issue(3) (Ziccardi, 2007), the fact of the matter
is that self-defense against non-State actors in the territory of
third-State runs counter to the prohibition on the use of force
and is outside of the personal scope of application of article
51. However, if the law governing the use of force fates States
with su󰀨ering attacks under these circumstances with their
hands tied, then, binding as it may be, it becomes a hindrance
in the performance of duties owed to citizens and an enabler
of irregular threats which empties the text and spirit of the UN
Charter and the core principles of modern international law.
Such a position would also be inconsistent with the
expansive caveat included in article 4 of A/RES/3314 (XXIX),
which could be reasonably interpreted to include -to borrow
the language from A/RES/2625 (XXV) as the denition of
aggression does- the inaction or toleration of irregular forces,
armed bands, or mercenaries meaning to violate the territorial
integrity of a third State. Also, the latter document upholds
the duty of a State to refrain “from acquiescing in organized
activities within its territory directed towards the commission
of such [acts of civil strife or terrorist acts in another State],
when the acts referred to in the present paragraph involve a
threat or use of force” (UN, 1975). It is worth noting that the
Annex to resolution A/RES/2625 (XXV) seems to be one of
the likeliest candidates to be considered jus
cogens and thus occupies a place of honor as
far as norms go, as evidenced by the Fourth
Report of the International Law Commission
on Peremptory Norms of General International
Law (ius cogens) on 2019 (International Law
Commission, 2019), and, in any event, it is
an indisputable expression of cornerstone
principles of international law.
From the above observed, the onus seems
to be on the territorial State to prevent and
deter the attack by non-State Actors (NSAs
going forward) upon the threatened State.
This much can be easily inferred. However,
this paper is not concerned with the duty of
the territorial State to avoid irregular armed
bands from inicting damage on the territorial
integrity or the political independence of third
States. It attempts to deal with the question
of resources available to the third State in
question -the recipient of the attack- when
the attack by NSAs is imminent or actual
and the territorial State fails to carry out
its duties to prevent the attack. Surely, the
answer cannot be, as pointed above, that
the would-be victim is powerless to preempt,
halt, or repel the attack. But, then again, such
an action appears to be at odds with article
51, which normatively excludes instances of
self-defense against actors other than States.
What if the answer to this conundrum is not
to be found on article 51 of the Constitution of
the UN, but rather on a simultaneously older
and newer regime?
This piece posits that the breach of
obligations owed to the territorial integrity
and sovereignty of the territorial State where
non-State armed groups can be justied if
the criteria of the state of necessity under the
regime of State responsibility is met. While
some authors opine that the regime of State
responsibility is incompatible with the activity
(1) Notwithstanding some attempts framed as customary law, such as those of the Caroline and Gorostiza Standards, which will be
discussed infra, especially in their allegedly normative dimension.
(2) Dened by the UN Secretariat as “very informal, condential gatherings which enable Security Council members to have a frank
and private exchange of views, within a exible procedural framework, with persons whom the inviting member or members of the
Council (who also act as the facilitators or convenors) believe it would be benecial to hear and/or to whom they may wish to convey
a message. They provide interested Council members an opportunity to engage in a direct dialogue with high representatives of
Governments and international organizations - often at the latter’s request - as well as non-State parties, on matters with which they
are concerned and which fall within the purview of responsibility of the Security Council” (UN, 2021, par. 2).
(3) See UNSC Resolutions S/RES/1373 (2001) of September 28th 2001 and S/RES/1368 (2001) in their preambulatory clauses.
IUS ET VERITAS 63
17
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
of the Security Council under the use of force regime, arguing
that the declaration of unlawfulness of a conduct is materially
di󰀨erent than the politic al assessment carried out by the Council
(Tsagourias, 2011), there is no impediment for the UNSC to
incorporate the examination of the operational requirements
for the excuse of necessity into its discussions, a point which
is discussed at large in this paper. This, in keeping with the
logic of articles 24, 39, and 51 of the UNC, which recognize
the organism’s near-monopoly on peace and security issues
and task it with receiving notications of self-defense or any
other situations concerning international peace and security,
acting in accordance with its guarantor role. Additionally, the
composition of the Council and its being bound by international
law would allow incorporation of the requisites laid down by
the ILCs 2001 Draft Articles on Responsibility of the State
for Internationally Wrongful Acts (DARSIWA going forward) in
assessing whether a state of necessity actually existed at the
moment the counterattacks were carried out and if the breach
is justied and thus not a violation of international peace and
security (and therefore of international law).
In order to answer these questions, this paper is divided into
three sections. The rst one is concerned with analyzing the
shortcomings of self-defense, as enshrined in the UN Charter,
to address the question of how States should respond to attacks
by NSAs on the territory of a third State that has not given its
consent for intervention. In doing so, this section explores the
limits of the inherence and non-constriction features of self-
defense as included in the Charter. It also reviews the existing
debate on the customary law on self-defense and the doctrinal
discussions concerning di󰀨erent standards that enable self-
defense against NSAs (with varying degrees of normativity)
such as the unwilling/unable doctrine and the Caroline and
Gorostiza incidents (and their ensuing doctrines), which have
contributed to shape the customary understanding of the law
of self-defense against NSAs.
The second section seeks to shed light on the institution of
the state of necessity and the current state of the art concerning
the doctrine to test its viability to exclude responsibility for
instances of self-defense against NSAs. To that end, it dissects
the conditions for the operation of the excuse as they have been
codied by the International Law Commission in 2001 and its
reception in international law. This part takes special note of
the relevant dicta of the International Court of Justice which
have substantially shaped the modern understanding of the
exception of state of necessity with a view to provide insights
into the correct interpretation of the requisites of essential nature
of the interest at stake, gravity, and imminence of the threat
that would then justify the breach and preclude wrongfulness.
This with a view to posit the compatibility of the doctrinal and
jurisprudential operation of said requisites with the conditions
of proportionality and necessity that ow from article 51 of the
UN Charter (Kretzmer, 2013).
The third section comprises the pièce de
resistance of this work. It explores how should
the claim of state of necessity operate (with
due regard to the previously laid conditions)
in lieu of the claim of inter-State self-defense
at the UNSC, without discarding the same
requirements of proportionality and necessity.
It also analyzes the issues of the authority of
the Council to entertain such a claim, based on
its primary responsibility for the maintenance
of international peace and security and its
ability to declare any given occurrence as a
threat to international peace and security and
consequently act on it.
The presumptive conclusion of this piece
is favorably oriented towards the legality (and
convenience) of enabling the plea of necessity
before the UNSC as a factor excluding
wrongfulness when actions preliminarily
constituting a breach of article 2(4) must be
taken in order to halt, repel, or maybe even
preempt an armed attack carried out by a NSA
from the territory of a third State, provided
that such a State is not allowing said actions
but refuses to permit the attacked State to
intervene, which leaves the originally attacked
State short of legal options to defend its own
territorial integrity and political independence.
The intention behind this proposition is to
provide a normative framework, compatible
with the law as it currently exists, that can
move the discussion away from contentious
and discretional standards with no normative
traction, such as the ‘unwilling and unable’
doctrine, and to provide a modicum of certainty
for the international community as to when
exceptions to territorial integrity can be
tolerated. In repurposing the UNSC by way of
extension of its material capability to analyze
instances of self-defense against NSAs in the
territory of a third non-consenting State, the
analysis and qualication of any given instance
of use of force becomes simultaneously subject
to legal and political scrutiny and may be held
accountable if it exceeds the limits. At the same
time, it constitutes an honest attempt to curtail
seemingly unfettered conduct by States when
conducting military operations in the territory
of others.
As a forethought, last year, a much
admired countrywoman took the law of
18 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
State responsibility out for a stroll in order to determine
whether consent was a defense or part of the denition of the
prohibition of force” (Paddeu, 2020), even if the key point of
that piece is only tangent to the discussion proposed here, her
conclusion serves as the perfect starting point of this paper:
any use of force which is inconsistent with the UN Charter
system is illegal and consent (or necessity in this case) is a
defense -or a justication- to exclude responsibility for the
breach. Therefore, and in the interest of safeguarding the
territorial integrity and political independence of the defending
State, recourse must be had to already existing valid law if
self-defense is to be claimed against NSAs in the territory
of a third State without its consent, and the UN Charter and
international law are to be upheld at all.
Additionally, this paper builds substantially on Terry Gill
and Kinga Tibori-Szabó’s paper of 2019, which outlined in
exquisite detail the operation of necessity in the context of the
customary law governing self-defense against NSAs in the
territory of a third non-consenting State. In it, they claimed
that “necessity () serve[s] as both the driver and the limiting
function of the exercise of self-defense” (Gill & Tibori-Szabó,
2019). This paper aims to take up the call made by the authors to
provide a normative framework susceptible of providing “some
adjustments” to our current thinking about necessity in order
to make it actionable in the existing Charter system governing
the use of force and self-defense.
2. The inadequacy of Charter
law governing the use of force to
encompass self-defense against
NSAs in the territory of a third State
without its consent
When thinking about the law governing the use of force in
international law, the rules appear to be self-evident. Outside
of UN Security Council (UNSC or the Council going forward)
authorization under a Chapter VII resolution or individual and
collective self-defense, the use of force against the territorial
integrity or political independence of another State, or in any
manner inconsistent with the purposes of the UN is prohibited(4)
(United Nations, 1945) and thus considered an internationally
wrongful act under the label of aggression, pursuant to articles
2(4) of the UN Charter (UNC going forward), and article 5(2) of
General Assembly resolution 3314 (XXIX) of
1974 (United Nations, 1974) which is largely
held to be reflective of customary norms
(Drnas de Clément, 2002) and even of jus
cogens rules (Torp Helmersen, 2014), which
has recently been welcomed into the fold of
international crimes under the competence of
the International Criminal Court.
In fact, article 3 of A/RES/3314 (XXIX)
singles out several actions which fall under
the category of aggression. For example:
invasion or attack of the territory of another
State, bombardment or use of any weapons
against the territory of another State, use of
force exceeding the limits of authorization of
the territorial State when it has consented
to military presence of the attacking State’s
forces, or allowing a State’s territory to be
used by a di󰀨erent State for attacking a third
State, just to name a few (United Nations,
1974). Upon revision a constant becomes
manifest: these banned uses of force are all
conceived as necessarily and exclusively
between States.
The system, dating back to the San
Francisco conference in 1945, was built by and
for States. It has a clear state-centric dynamic
embedded in it (Kotlik, 2017), reective of
the paradigm that governed international law
at the time (Gill & Tibori-Szabó, 2019); the
main (and almost sole) subjects of it were
States. Individuals or private groups were
held to have little or no agency in the legally-
relevant exchanges governed by this branch
of the law(5). As a result, the UN Charter (UNC
henceforth) system governing force does not
take into account the organized used of armed
violence carried out by or against non-State
entities when it is not tolerated or allowed
by the territorial State, which would then
necessarily fall under the ‘domestic matters
of the territorial State’ label to the chagrin of
the threatened or attacked State.
(4) Without prejudice to exceptions created by regional agreements like NATO, or the OAS which largely follow the same logic with
minor deviations. In the case of the Inter-American Treaty of Reciprocal Assistance and its potential application to situations other
than inter-State use of force. See Franck, T. (1970) “Who Killed Article 2(4)? Or: Changing Norms Governing the Use of Force by
States”. American Journal of International Law, 64(5), 809-837, however this point will be revisited later on in this paper.
(5) Except maybe in the realms of international criminal law, international humanitarian law and international human rights law, all of
which were prominent features of the mid-20th century’s legal landscape with the Nuremberg and Tokyo war crimes tribunals and
their ensuing developments.
IUS ET VERITAS 63
19
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
Since its inception, the UN’s use of force system was
conceived as a mechanism to sort out disputes between States
that decided to renounce war as means of dispute settlement.
Picking up where the Kellogg-Briand Pact left o󰀨, the San
Francisco Conference of 1945 was inaugurated by President
Truman to the following tune:
() The essence of our problem here is to provide sensible
machinery for the settlement of disputes among nations, Without
this, peace cannot exist. We can no longer permit any nation or
group of nations to attempt to settle their arguments with bombs
and bayonets (Truman, 1945, par. 35).
This same spirit, which evidently guided the endeavors of the
San Francisco Conference, is the reection of the commitments
made at Yalta and Dumbarton Oaks (Britannica, 2021). Notice,
in the latter, articles 3 and 4 of Chapter VIII, section A, about
pacic settlement of disputes among States. The intent to
regulate was clear: uses of force between States should be
banned by the future organization to replace the League of
Nations. These commitments were the forebears of the current
UNC use of force system. However, and after more than seven
decades, the dynamics of the international arena have outgrown
the material scope of application of the Charters use of force
system by and large.
Interstate armed conflict, whether aggressive or not,
within the meaning of common article 2 of the 1949 Geneva
Conventions, have increasingly become an exceptional
situation. Much in the same way as isolated uses of force
between States falling short of that threshold. This could be
celebrated, partly, as a success of the UN system (if one feels
obsequious) or as a consequence of a myriad other factors
having to do with complex interdependence (Keohane & Nye,
2000). However, conict remains a constant, even if it changes
in formand parties. This observation highlights the apparent
mismatch between Charter law governing the use of force
and current reality, which now encompasses actors other than
States.
Arguably, the reference in article 51 to the non-constriction
of the inherent right of self-defense of States was designed
to respect dimensions of operation outside of the scope of
application of the article itself (Bethlehem, 2021). This would
mean that the scope of customary self-defense at the time of
the drafting of the Charter may have indeed exceeded that of
only interstate uses of force(6). However, as observed by Gill and
Tibori-Szabó (2019), several authors argue that the limitation
implied by the wording of article 51 UNC was deliberately
intended to reduce the scope of action of self-defense even
beyond the Charter(Tladi, 2013). As pointed out: “[o]ne of
the controversies regarding the e󰀨ect of the
Charter on the pre-1945 right of self-defense
concerns NSAGs and whether these groups
can qualify as authors of an armed attack”
(Gill & Tibori-Szabó, 2019, p. 475).
The question raised by the authors
follows the logic of broadening the material
and personal scope of application of article
51 to see whether the right of self-defense
can encompass armed attacks by NSAs.
Even with the diverging opinions of scholarly
commentators on the matter, the application
of interpretation methods enshrined in the
Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties of
1969 (VCLT) on articles 31-33 would seem
to foreclose such attempt. The Charter is
an international treaty signed by States and
incapable of producing obligations outside of
that personal scope. More to the point, the
travaux préparatoires of the UNC are clear
evidence that:
[T]he drafters primary objective was to regulate
State behavior rather than address the dangers
posed by NSAGs. Accordingly, during the
drafting process, the principal discussions
regarding article 51 centered on the concerns
of Latin American States that the Charter and
the powers of the Security Council did not
supersede their regional arrangements for
collective self-defense (Tibori-Szabó, 2011,
p. 474).
Similarly, the personal scope of
applicability of article 51 was not discussed
during the San Francisco Conference. As Gills
and Tibori-Szabó report, an earlier draft of the
article included the precision that it referred to
attacks by a State against any other member
State, but it was later dropped without a
reason on the record for it (2019). This silence,
while in and of itself not terribly indicative of
anything, allows for context to be brought to
bear on account of the lack of literal or textual
interpretations to be had. Thus, systematic
interpretation forces the reader to address
article 51 in the context of article 2(4) of the
same document. In the latter, the use of force
is prohibited among States, and it would stand
to reason that, being the exception to article
(6) This idea certainly nds support in pre-existing doctrines and standards concerning uses of force against non-State actors in the
territory of third States such as those laid out in the Rainbow Warrior case, or the Caroline and Gorostiza Incidents. The ensuing
standards will be explored in more depth later on the piece.
20 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
attacks occurring in the territorial jurisdiction
of the attacked State.
Another point to consider by those
defending a parallel customary regime allowing
for the claim of self-defense tantamount to
that of article 51 UNC is the Charters non-
supersession clause located in article 103.
In principle, this rule would preclude the
possibility of change in the terms laid out in the
Charter by any other international agreement
which would then negate the legality of the
so-called parallel customary regime if it runs
counter to the exclusively inter-State domain
of article 51. However, there is contention
on whether article 103 UNC is applicable
to customary law or whether it only applies
to international agreements understood as
treaties (Glennon, 2001) which would render
this particular argument inconclusive, but still
worth considering.
Regardless of the conclusion on the
interpretive discrepancy of article 103 UNC,
another line of defense that would go against
the possibility of both the enlargement of
article 51 UNC by way of practice and against
the existence of a stand-alone customary
permission. This would be the purported jus
cogens nature of the prohibition of the use
of force (Torp Helmersen, 2014). While the
determination and e󰀨ects of jus cogens rules
are still hotly contested (ILC, 2016), one thing
is clear: no norm of jus cogens character may
be derogated from unless such modication
comes from a subsequent peremptory rule.
Naturally, this would apply squarely should
the contending norm be found in a treaty (as
per article 53 VCLT), which is notably not the
case here, nevertheless it is still noteworthy
that there is resistance by the normative
establishment to accept changes to rules
endowed with such superior character(9).
Building on this, the last few years have
witnessed the resurgence of the so-called
2(4), article 51 would inexplicably have a wider ratio personae
spectrum, this same reasoning is exhibited by authors such as
Mary Ellen O’Conell (2013), and Rona & Walla (2013).
A State-centric reading of the result of the joint reading of
articles 2(4) and 51 of the UNC, in line with the freedom principle
enshrined in the PCIJs Lotus Case (1927), would thus mean
that if not explicitly prohibited, then the resort to self-defense
against NSAs in the territory of a third non-consenting State
would be lawful (Gill & Tibori-Szabó, 2019). However, upon
close examination, this view doesn’t hold. This is because any
use of force conducted against a NSA will necessarily occur on
the territory of a third State(7) and will then amount to a violation
of article 2(4) UNC in prejudice of the territorial State unless an
exception or justication can be proven.
This latter point also ts within a teleological reading of the
UNC. The object and purpose of article 51 in the larger context
of the UNC is evident from article 2 of the Charter, which lays
out the principles of the Organization. The very object of the
treaty is to preempt uses of force against the territorial integrity
and political independence of member States. The discrepancy
between the target of the attack (the NSA and not the State)
and the e󰀨ects, forcibly su󰀨ered by the territorial State, don’t
appear to be distinguishable, even if the case has been made
by authors such as Trapp (Trapp, 2015)(8). The problem with
using intentionality of targeting as a rationale for toleration is
that it results impossible to ascertain from an objective model
of responsibility, such as the one prevalent in international law.
One further avenue to analyze whether the use of force
system of the UNC can cater to the situation under study is
that of subsequent practice (under the VCLT as complementary
and subsidiary method of interpretation) relative to UN Charter
law (Gill & Tibori-Szabó, 2019). As is usual in these instance,
scholarly commentary covers both positions. In the a󰀩rmative,
authors such as Murphy (2002) and Antonopoulos (2008) posit
that the pre-Charter customary admissibility of self-defense
against NSAs in the territory of a third non-consenting State
remains untouched and therefore, while separate from the UNs
use of force system, the exercise of self-defense is legal. This
is unconvincing insofar as it adds nothing to consider in the
evolution of practice surrounding the UN Charter but rather just
o󰀨ers the existence of a parallel and unconstrained customary
regime. Another shortcoming of this position is that it does not
take into account the location of the NSA and covers only those
(7) With the potential exception of uses of force carried out in res communis places such as the High Seas or Outer Space, which -on
account of lack of regulation in one case, and lack of potentiality, in the other- are excluded from the analysis of this piece.
(8) The main point of this proposition is that self-defense against NSAs may be permissible to the extent that the territorial State itself
is not targeted.
(9) In its 2019 report on peremptory rules of general international law of the ILC, the Special Rapporteur, Mr. Dire Tladi, has put forth the
notion that jus cogens rules may not be derogated by contravening custom or desuetude. While the author remains unconvinced with
the identication and operation of this special category of norms, it is noteworthy that institutions which do support it are convinced
that these norms may not be derogated from under any circumstances.
IUS ET VERITAS 63
21
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
‘unwilling or unable’ doctrine on the realm of jus ad bellum.
While articulations along the same lines can be found as far
back as 1970 by the Nixon administration in the US (Heller,
2019), 1976 by Israel on its Entebbe raid (O’Connell, 2019), or
1981, again by Israel, concerning its armed activities in Lebanon
(Gill & Tibori-Szabó, 2019), it has become prominent in the post
9/11 world and especially in the context of the so-called ‘War
on Terror’ that followed the invasion of Afghanistan. It also was
(even if not mentioned out loud) the preponderant subject of the
above mentioned Arria Formula meeting convened by Mexico
on February 2021.
The ‘unwilling and/or unable’ proposition is built upon the
premise that the territorial State has an active duty to prevent
any damage caused to third States originating on its own
territory, following on the ICJs Corfu Channel Case (ICJ, 1949)
recognition of the international obligation not to cause or allow
harm to other States, which is also enshrined in A/RES/2625
(XXV) of 1970 as pointed out above. Thus, the doctrine posits
that “a victim state has the right to engage in lawful extra-
territorial self-defense when the host state is unwilling and/or
unable to mitigate or suppress the threat posed by domestic
NSAs” (Williams, 2013, p. 620).
The doctrine allegedly nds its pedigree as an update
of the Caroline standard (DeLaurentis, 2021), although this
genealogy is a bit doubtful (Heller, 2019). It originally posited
that anticipatory self-defense against NSAs, in order to be
lawful, should comprise “a necessity of self-defense, instant,
overwhelming, leaving no choice of means, and no moment
for deliberation” (Webster, 1837). Precisely because of the
immediacy of the action required and its overwhelmingness
and gravity. The doctrine was held to be a lawful exception to
the then-not so absolute prohibition on the use of force and
went on to constitute the foundation of the customary law of
self-defense in the pre-Charter era.
However, in trying to expand the material reach of application
of the Caroline test to justify the ‘unwilling and/or unable’
doctrine, even if taking into account other relevant incidents
like the Gorostiza standard which notoriously centered the
discussion around the need to prove necessity before allowing
extra-territorial self-defense (Gurmendi, 2020), the test of time
has been unfavorable towards the exception. The paucity of
general practice seems to belie the notion that it has attained
customary character (Chachko & Deeks, 2016), much in the
same way that the invocation of the exception has been all but
consistent (Gill & Tibori-Szabó, 2019). Additionally, it is riddled
with ambiguities which threaten international
peace and security in the absence of clear
regulation. The appreciation put forth by
Sharma and Agarwal hits the mark when they
comment that the eet utile of the doctrine
is to circumvent the need to obtain the host
state’s consent. This can naturally threaten the
international order absent a strict regulation
(Sharma & Agarwal, 2020). The authors
further posit that the doctrine -due to its
inconsistent invocation and application- has
failed to garner customary status (Sharma &
Agarwal, 2020).
The ‘unwilling and/or unable’ doctrine
presents a perfect example of why trying to
articially expand the limits of article 51 UNC is
incompatible with the legal regime laid out by the
treaty itself. The arguments put forth by States,
such as France, Denmark, Egypt, Lebanon,
Colombia, Uganda, or India, doubting the
legality of the doctrine is highly telling (Chachko
& Deeks, 2016) in that they situate Charter
law as the starting point for any discussion
on self-defense, which then complicates any
attempt at enlarging the scope of application
(personal and material) of article 51 UNC. These
sentiments are echoed and expanded further by
States such as Mexico (who convened the Arria
Formula meeting), who have outright rejected
the legality of the doctrine on the same basis
(De la Fuente, 2021).
On the camp of those who argue against
the legality of claiming self-defense in terms
of article 51 UNC as a right to be exercised
against NSAs located in the territory of a third
non-consenting State, the arguments put forth
by Kunz (1947), Stahn (2003), Kammerhofer
(2007) and Orakhelashvili (2015) ring most
persuasive. In sum, these authors support the
conclusion that the use of force system built
into the UN Charter was designed exclusively
for inter-State exchanges of violence(10) and
thus negate the possibility of self-defense
being a feasible or legal claim in the particular
instance of scrutiny of this paper.
(10) With the notable inclusion of instances of armed attack carried out by non-State actors only if attribution or substantial involvement of
a State can be proven. This scenario has been the subject of ample discussion and has been endorsed by the International Court of
Justice in rulings like the Nicaragua case (Nicaragua v. USA) and the Armed Activities case (DR Congo v. Rwanda). In both instances,
the Court has found that if there is a su󰀩cient level of control or involvement of the State in the activities of the armed group then
the actions may be attributable to the State for determination of international responsibility.
22 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
of an attack is not a State, but the o󰀨ense still
originates within the territory of another State
and must be dealt with in its territory. However,
all is not lost. There is law outside of the UN
Charter (and compatible with it) that may be
used for this exact purpose, without prejudice
to the system of use of force contained inthe
treaty. Enter in the ILC’s Draft Articles on
Responsibility of the State for Internationally
Wrongful Acts article 25: the plea of necessity.
3. The state of necessity
as a circumstance
precluding wrongfulness
under the law of State
responsibility
As a forethought to this section, it should
be noted that in the case under analysis,
there is no adequate or materially coincident
regulation (conventional, customary, or
otherwise) that caters to the specic situation
of exercising any type of self-defense against
NSAs located in the territory of a third State
that refuses permission to deal with the
threat. As shown above, Charter law and its
customary equivalent governing the use of
force do not provide sensible alternatives to
this situation. In absence of any regulation in
primary rules, the default option(12) becomes
the Draft Articles on the Responsibility of
the State for Internationally Wrongful Acts
(Crawford, 2019).
Furthermore, before addressing the
proposition of the plea of necessity in the
context of the DARSIWA as a more deft way
to navigate instances of self-defense against
NSAs in the territory of a third non-consenting
State than conventional self-defense in the
Charter context, it is useful to note (as detailed
above) that diverse attempts have been made
to provide frameworks to enable the practice.
Most notable from the academic trenches is
the discussion started by Daniel Bethlehem
In practice, the United Nations Security Council, tasked
with qualifying the legality and correctness of instances of self-
defense under article 51 UNC, has been less than receptive to
claims of self-defense against NSAs in the rare opportunities
when it has said anything at all. Resolutions S/RES/273 of 1969,
S/RES/294 of 1971 dealing with this exact claim being put forth
by Portugal or resolutions S/RES/265 of 1969, S/RES/313 of
1972, or S/RES/467 of 1980 concerning the alleged exercise of
extra-territorial self-defense by Israel bear witness to the little
sympathy the Council holds for this position. However, as will
be noted below, the agency of the Council as a law-determining
body remains contested and the politics that are an integral
part of its operation make it di󰀩cult to ascertain whether the
rejections is founded on politics or on law.
On a similar note, and (mostly) unburdened by the cloud of
politics, the ICJ has also observed that it does not look kindly
to the claim of self-defense under article 51 UNC when used
against non-State actors. In the Wall advisory opinion and
the Armed Activities ruling, the ICJ displayed discomfort with
applying the right of self-defense to non-State attacks lacking
a clear connection to a State (Arimatsu & Schmitt, 2021). This
would conrm that, in the Court’s opinion, the claim of self-
defense under article 51 of the UNC is restricted to inter-State
exchanges of force(11).
As shown above, and recognizing that the issue has
warranted substantial discussion, its safe to say that caution
advises against the legality of claiming self-defense when the
author of the attack is not a State. Much more so if the purported
actions to repel, halt, or preempt the attack are to have e󰀨ects
or be carried out in the territory of a third State that has not
consented to the action and regardless of whether the territorial
State has complied with its duty to not tolerate or harbor NSAs
hostile to the defending State.
That is, of course, a matter of law, which, as pointed out
earlier, runs counter to logic and to the defending State’s
own right to the respect of its territorial integrity and political
independence. As a matter of fact, the proposition that the
defending State’s hands are tied, and it is fated to su󰀨er the
attack out of respect for the territorial integrity of the territorial
State is entirely antithetic to its legitimate expectations under
article 2(4) UNC and also absurd.
The conclusion then, is that Charter law governing self-
defense is largely inapplicable to situations where the author
(11) In the interest of precision, it must be annotated that the ICJ, in the Wall opinion and the Armed Activities Case, has only condemned
instances of self-defense carried out against the State harboring the NSAs and not the NSAs themselves. However, this position
could be held to reinforce the impossibility to separate the personal and territorial aspects of self-defense against NSAs in the territory
of a third non-consenting State, as pointed out above. Additionally, the silence of the Court as to this specic situation (which it did
not include as a lawful option) should be read in keeping with the integrity and superiority of the prohibition of the use of force in
substantive terms.
(12) Especially since the articles restrict their applicability if the particular material regime contains any lex specialis dealing with declaration
of responsibility.
IUS ET VERITAS 63
23
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
and hosted by the American Journal of International Law of the
so-called ‘Bethlehem Principles’ (Bethlehem, 2012). Su󰀩ce it to
say that the best argument against Bethlehem’s proposition is
that it has failed to generate cohesion among States who nd
themselves attempting to justify their attacks on the territory
of third States (even if bits and pieces of the argument appear
sparsely every now and then in di󰀨erent doctrinal enunciations).
The most cogent expression of the inadequacies of that
proposition is that:
[D]espite their constant invocation, the notions of necessity,
imminence, and proportionality are fraught with conceptual
ambiguit y and are notoriously di󰀩cult to apply in practice. By relying
heavily on necessity, imminence, and proportionality, Bethlehem
imports these di󰀩culties into his principles (Akande & Lieänder,
2013, p. 569).
The criticisms to this proposition are not exclusive to
Bethlehem’s principles. As noted above, neither State practice,
expert commentary, nor even jurisprudence have so far come
up with a regime well-suited and properly tailored to cater to this
very particular situation. That is, presumably, the reason why
exercises like the Arria Formula meeting convened by Mexico in
February 2021 are simultaneously so useful and so problematic.
The lack of clarity and precision ailing the components of self-
defense, in the context of its invocation against NSAs, make it
impractical and cumbersome and di󰀩cult to assess even after
the fact.
This paper contends that self-defense (be it within the
Charter context or without) is ill-suited to answer to the new
realities a󰀨ecting the current conventional and customary use
of force dynamics. As observed earlier, this normative gap
would force the conclusion that States are fated to su󰀨er harm
when the particular conditions studied here present themselves.
Within the very context of the ILC’s Draft Articles, article 21
covers self-defense as a ground for exclusion of responsibility,
but as it was mentioned before, that system is designed for
inter-State instances of self-defense and therefore does not
govern the specic case analyzed in this situation, this becomes
evident in comment (5) of article 21 of the DARSIWA which
claims that “(5) The essential e󰀨ect of article 21 is to preclude the
wrongfulness of conduct of a State acting in self-defense vis-à-
vis an attacking State. ()” (ILC, 2001). This occurs because the
rules concerning self-defense in the Articles essentially copy the
Charter system of self-defense. In fact, the reference to article
51 UNC is explicitly built into article 21 of the DARSIWA, as is
the subjection to the requisites of proportionality and necessity
under the UN Charter law.
As a matter of legal logic, claiming self-defense when
the author of the attack is not another State creates issues
of contradiction with article 2(4) of the UN Charter. If one
State’s right of self-defense is exercised, then there is a
necessary infringement upon the right of territorial integrity of
the territorial State. Simply put a defending
State cannot repel, halt, or counter an attack
launched by an NSA on the territory of a
third State without exercising force in the
territory of that State and therefore breaching
its territorial sovereignty. This because the
UN Charter bars self-defense against actors
other than States. This ies in the face of
Aristotle’s logical non-contradiction principle,
where two opposing premises cannot be
simultaneously and entirely true. This is
precisely why self-defense is designed
as an exception to the right of territorial
integrity of the territorial State (when it is
itself the attacker) which has opened up to
the infringement by virtue of its own violation
of the other State’s right to territorial integrity
or political independence. The resemblance
to countermeasures is, evidently, uncanny.
This is because it is the aggression of the
attacking State that gives way to the right of
self-defense of the defending State. That is,
however, not the case when attacker is not a
State. The ILC espouses a similar logic in its
commentated version of the Draft Articles. It
goes on to say:
(1) The existence of a general principle
admitting self-defense as an exception to
the prohibition against the use of force in
international relations is undisputed. Article 51
of the Charter of the United Nations preserves
a State’sinherent right” of self-defense in
the face of an armed attack and forms part of
the denition of the obligation to refrain from
the threat or use of force laid down in Article
2, paragraph 4. Thus, a State exercising its
inherent right of self-defense as referred to in
Article 51 of the Charter is not, even potentially,
in breach of Article 2, paragraph 4 (ILC, 2001,
p. 24).
Read in the context of article 21 as a
whole (especially in its’ 5th and 6th comments),
this exclusion of breach can only operate
when the hostile act occurs amongst States.
Given that self-defense is an exception to
the unlawfulness of the use of force, such an
exception may not be expanded absent the
clear intent to do so on the part of States. To
date, this issue is hotly contested as shown
above, and no clear articulations of opinio
juris su󰀩cient in number seem to exist, as
the coverage of February’s Arria Formula has
conclusively shown.
24 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
The inadequacies of self-defense under Charter law and its
copycat in article 21 of the DARSIWA yield no useful answers
to the question of self-defense against NSAs operating from the
territory of a third non-consenting State. However, a sensible
alternative may -as promised at the outset of this piece- be found
in article 25 of the DARSIWA covering the plea of necessity.
The article in question reads:
Article 25. Necessity
1. Necessity may not be invoked by a State as a ground for
precluding the wrongfulness of an act not in conformity with an
international obligation of that State unless the act:
(a) is the only way for the State to safeguard an essential interest
against a grave and imminent peril; and
(b) does not seriously impair an essential interest of the State or
States towards which the obligation exists, or of the international
community as a whole.
2. In any case, necessity may not be invoked by a State as a ground
for precluding wrongfulness if:
(a) the international obligation in question excludes the possibility
of invoking necessity; or
(b) the State has contributed to the situation of necessity (ILC,
2001, p. 80).
As observed by Arimatsu and Schmitt, “[n]ecessity is a
core principle of international law that operates in diverse ways
within di󰀨erent legal regimes. For example, it is a condition
(the law governing the use of force), a foundational principle
(international humanitarian law), a limitation (international
human right law), and a legal defense (international criminal
law)” (Arimatsu & Schmitt, 2021, p. 1182). Being a core principle
of the normative system, its existence prior to its inclusion in
the 2001 DARSIWA is pretty much uncontested by both the
International Court of Justice and the ILC (Arimatsu & Schmitt,
2021) and by scholarly commentary at large. Evidence of its
role in international law can be found as far back as Grotius,
who wrote of its operation in the context of jus in bello (Boed,
2000), or -in the context of self-defense- in instances like the
Caroline incident or the Gorostiza Pamphlet (Gurmendi, 2020).
In its modern sense, the ILC o󰀨ers a denition of necessity
in the context of justications in the following way:
(1) The term “necessity” (tat de ncessite) is used to denote those
exceptional cases where the only way a State can safeguard an
essential interest threatened by a grave and imminent peril is, for
the time being, not to perform some other international obligation
of lesser weight or urgency. Under conditions narrowly dened in
article 25, such a plea is recognized as a circumstance precluding
wrongfulness (ILC, 2001, p. 24).
Note how, from the outset, necessity is
presented by the DARSIWA as a negative
formulation. This gives credit to its extremely
exceptional nature (Paliouras, 2016) which
has also been noted by the World Court
on its Gabcikovo-Nagymaros Project case
when it highlighted its very exceptional
character (1997). The wording utilized by
the Commission certainly conrms its last
resort nature, not unlike the one that would
be made under circumstances so grave
that left no moment for deliberation and no
choice of means. This exceptional nature
is compatible with the pacta sunt servanda
owed to third States and is precisely why it
makes for a palatable way to navigate the
situation presented in this paper.
From its debut in classical law systems and
to this day, the state of necessity is indicative
of the general unlawfulness of the action taken
in the specic context in a logic akin to that
of justications or excuses (Paddeu, 2020).
However, recourse to it is justied insofar as
it seeks to protect a more valuable interest
than the one being harmed. Boed writes in
this context that:
[W]hen a threat to self-preservation arose,
it was considered justified to take any steps
necessary to preserve one’s existence,
even if such steps would have been unlawful
had they been taken in the absence of a
threat to self-preservation (Boed, 2000,
p. 4).
As observed by the same author, “the
balancing test in the provisionally adopted
text of article 33 of the ILC’s Draft Articles
on State Responsibility is designed to weigh
inconsistent interests of two States ()(13)
(Boed, 2000, p. 3), from there it follows,
that the drafters of the articles identied the
norms of State responsibility as exible in
deference to essential interests of States
without necessarily making them trump
cards that would void of content and binding
character the obligations of the State vis a
vis each other.
(13) See also Report of the International Law Commission on the Work of its Twenty-Seventh Session, U.N. Doc. A/10010/Rev.1 (1975),
51-59, U.N. Doc. AICN.4/SER.Al1975/Add.1; Report of the International Law Commission on the Work of its Thirty-Second Session,
U.N. Doc. A/35/10 (1980), 26- 34, U.N. Doc.AICN.4/SER.A/1980/Add.1.
IUS ET VERITAS 63
25
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
Its outstanding character has to do with its linkage, in classical
times, to the innate right of self-preservation which is natural
to every State. In fact, Boed (2000), goes on to note that Hugo
Grotius himself accounts for the recognition of the right to self-
preservation as far back as roman law, and that it was later picked
up by the social contract writers such as Locke, Hobbes, and
Rousseau. Thus, the historical logic behind the state of necessity
is not to remove the unlawfulness of the action taken, but rather
to shift the discussion towards the necessity that justies the
illegality in a particular factual context. As a consequence of this
shift in the terms, responsibility for the trespass cannot be exacted
by the aggravated party because of the extraordinary nature of
the threat or harm caused to the State claiming the operation of
necessity. This is consistent with the nature of international law
as a system of voluntary self-limitation (Jellinek, 1880) enshrined
in the Lotus Principle (PCIJ, 1927).
However, not every whim of the State can fall under this
normative exception and the reach of necessity has been
narrowly dened ever since its Grotian inclusion. Rodick
identies six conditions in the writings of the seminal scholar
for the exception of necessity in the context of inter-State
warfare: (1) absence of criminal intent, (2) existence of
real danger to vital interests, (3) temporal imminence, (4)
proportionality, (5) consideration to the equities involved, and
(6) duty to e󰀨ect reparations whenever possible (Rodick, 1928).
Much of these still permeate the ILC’s modern conception of
the state of necessity and resonate with the doctrinal requisites
imposed on self-defense -as an exercise of the fundamental
right to self-preservation of the State- under the aegis of
article 51 of the UN Charter, even if theyre not legislated into
the requisites.
It is precisely because of this higher normative threshold
that it seems to o󰀨er a framework that is simultaneously
respectful of the legitimate expectations of the territorial
State to have its rights under article 2(4) UNC respected while
enabling a non-condemning alternative for the defending State
when an attack by a NSA physically situated in the territory of
the ‘attacked’ State occurs. In raising the bar by demanding a
stricter scrutiny of the existence of necessity, the defending
State need not be hopelessly subject to attacks by NSAs
without being able to see to its own essential interests in the
face of an uncooperative territorial State. In the same train of
thought, it should be noted that the ILCs 5th comment under
article 25 references the Caroline incident and qualies it not
as self-defense, but rather as a clear-cut case of the operation
of the state of necessity (ILC, 2001) which
is exactly the claim put forth by this piece.
3.1. The conditions for operation of article
25 of the DARSIWA
The forcible conclusion (or perhaps the cause)
of the very existence of the state of necessity as
a circumstance that precludes wrongfulness,
is that it safeguards “the most important of
these fundamental rights of States [which is]
that of existence, which involves the rights
of self-preservation and defense” (Hershey,
1927, p. 231). This is perfectly aligned with
the ontology of the exception in that it seeks
to protect essential interests of the State
that may run counter to its obligations and in
detriment of the rights of other States. In order
to achieve this, necessity requires a balancing
of protected rights against those that would
su󰀨er from the breach.
This is precisely the quid of the issue, as
observed by Boed, “the balancing test in the
provisionally adopted text of article 33(14) of the
ILC’s Draft Articles on State Responsibility is
designed to weigh inconsistent interests of two
States ()”(15) (Boed, 2000, p. 4), from this it
follows, that the ILC drafters meant to codify
a exible regime, simultaneously mindful of
the most important interests of States without
negating the e󰀩cacy of international obligations.
Fenwick describes the di󰀩culties of the
balancing test in writing that “[t]he conict of
international rights thus resulting is governed
by a few general principles of law, which are,
however, so vague as to leave it an open
question in many cases whether the right
of one has justied a breach of the right of
the other” (Fenwick, 1965, pp. 142-143).
This is exactly applicable, letter by letter, to
the current law governing self-defense and
even more so to the question of whether
self-defense is admissible vis a vis non-State
actors in the territory of a third non-consenting
State, with one minor caveat: the defense of
essential interests of the State, like survival,
is not understood in the context of the law of
(14) Now article 25.
(15) See also Report of the International Law Commission on the Work of its Twenty-Seventh Session, U.N. Doc. A/10010/Rev.1 (1975),
51-59, U.N. Doc. AICN.4/SER.Al1975/Add.1; Report of the International Law Commission on the Work of its Thirty-Second Session,
U.N. Doc. A/35/10 (1980), 26-34, U.N. Doc.AICN.4/SER.A/1980/Add.1.
26 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
responsibility as a right(16), but rather as a way to evade the
responsibility that accompanies the breach of obligation (Ago,
1980).
Ago’s conclusion that self-preservation is -operationally-
an excuse rather than a right is seemingly backed by judicial
practice (Cheng, 2006) and by a noteworthy lack of substantial
State protest.
Notwithstanding the rough edges in its denition, at least
there’s widespread agreement on the requirements necessary
for the plea of necessity to operate. These are laid out in article
25(1)(a) of the DARSIWA and are composed of (1) the essential
nature of the protected interest, (2) the gravity of the harm
threatened or inicted, and (3) the need of immediate action.
From among these three requirements, the rst one poses
severe challenges in terms of interpretation. The ILC itself
declined to provide a denition or a metric of comparison as to
what constitutes an ‘essential’ interest (ILC, 2001). This lack of
denition ought to be interpreted as a deference to the subjective
classication of the State, and as a function of the di󰀩culty to
agree on a xed set of situations meriting such a classication.
The preference for the case-by-case analysis of each scenario
lends credence to the idea that the nature of ‘essential’ of the
interest is context-dependent and should be thus assessed. This
deference to the State is not, however, without limits. The ILC
has opined that “[t]he extent to which a given interest is essential
depends on all the circumstances and cannot be prejudged. It
extends to particular interests of the State and its people, as
well as of the international community as a whole” (ILC, 2001).
In other words, while the burden of proving the essential nature
of the interest is on the claimant of the necessity, the analysis
of whether the interest is fundamental must be carried out in
light of the context and circumstances surrounding the situation.
The dangers in this position are manifold. It opens the door
for pronouncing virtually anything as an essential interest and
therefore negating the extraordinary character of the plea of
necessity. Regardless, the very fact that the essential nature
of the interest ought to be demonstrated in order for the claim
of necessity to hold, provides a much stricter standard than
that of the law governing self-defense, where any armed
attack satisfying a minimal degree of gravity will warrant lawful
retaliation(17). This is already a rst positive for necessity as a
normative framework to complement the law governing the
use of force in the UNC context. Precisely
because of its exceptional nature and the need
for an interest above mere topical allegations
of sovereignty to be demonstrated, it o󰀨ers
-at least- a chance for differentiated and
strict scrutiny where self-defense cannot.
Additionally, the fact that the argument for the
essential character of the interest ought to be
put forth after the unlawful act does not, at
all, subtract from the usefulness of it. By any
metric, if the essential nature of the interest
threatened or attack is not proven, then the
justication fails and the action is outright
illegal, with the necessary consequences
ensuing, much as it can happen when a
claim of self-defense under article 51 UNC is
brought to the UNSC.
As to the second and third requisites
codied by the ILC, namely that of the gravity
and imminence of the peril, the Commission
went on to add that:
Whatever the interest may be, however, it is only
when it is threatened by a grave and imminent
peril that this condition is satised. The peril
has to be objectively established and not merely
apprehended as possible. In addition to being
grave, the peril has to be imminent in the sense
of proximate (ILC, 2001, p. 83).
While these conceptual contributions from
the ILC surely are useful in ascertaining the
limits of operation of the state of necessity,
they contribute little to actually dening what
gravity and imminence are. The exact legal
meaning and import of those two words is the
subject of several rivers’ worth of ink courtesy
of scholarly writing and then some more
brought by international jurisprudence(18).
If self-defense claims under article 51 of
the UN Charter may be used as a mirror for
the operation of the plea of necessity when it
concerns response to armed attacks by NSAs
(and the contention here is that they can to a
certain extent), then to look for orientation on
(16) Which it may very well be, if seen as a function of delegated sovereignty as suggested by modern contractualists (Dobos, 2011)
and also as a consequence of the designation of self-defense as an inherent right under article 51 of the UN Charter. That point is,
nevertheless, besides the scope of this article since the operation of the regime of State responsibility characterizes this right as an
excuse to evade responsibility and not as a ‘‘clash of rights’’.
(17) As occurs with virtually any letter addressed to the Security Council concerning an article 51 notication where mention to the events
that triggered the exercise of self-defense are typically never discussed and, at best, barely mentioned in passing.
(18) Specically on the subject of imminence, the very existence of incredibly robust volumes of results for any search for “preventive
self-defense” or “anticipatory self-defense” bear witness to the diverging views concerning the necessary temporal threshold of a
threat in order for measures to be available to the threatened State.
IUS ET VERITAS 63
27
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
the requisites of gravity and imminence the emphasis should
be put on the proxy concepts of necessity and proportionality
because of their intimate relationship. The rationale behind
the likening of these requisites ows from the notion that the
gravity and imminence of the peril provide the metric to assess
the necessity and proportionality of the response in a sort-of
symbiotic normative relationship. If the peril or threat is minor
or trivial, then any armed response to it will necessarily be
disproportionate. If the threat cannot be objectively assessed
to exist, then the response is unnecessary(19).
As the ICJ observed in the Wall opinion, under the UN
Charter any armed attack by another State triggers the right
of self-defense (ICJ, 2004). Regardless of this the Court
has occasionally analyzed whether the original use of force
constituted a grave violation of article 2(4) giving way to the
exercise of self-defense and accordingly qualied the necessity
and proportionality of the defensive force employed. By doing
this, the Court has provided -maybe without actively meaning
to- a judicial standard to qualify both the gravity and (to a lesser
extent) the imminence of the peril that would then trigger the
right of self-defense (or the plea of necessity here). Note that
in the Oil Platforms case the ICJ was unpersuaded by the
US’ arguments concerning the obiter on the use of force and
ended up nding that the US’ actions were neither necessary
nor proportional under the circumstances as appraised by
the Court, which surprisingly enough, engaged in a scrutiny
seemingly more akin to the plea of necessity under the
DARSIWA than that of self-defense, As hinted by Taft, the Court
seemed to suggest that unless a minimal threshold of gravity is
evident in the use of force, then self-defense will not become an
option because it would be unnecessary and disproportionate
(Taft, 2004). Similar conclusions were reached by the Court in
the Armed Activities on the Territory of the Congo case, it found
that the preconditions for the exercise of self-defense were not
satised and, in consequence, it was not tasked with analyzing
whether Uganda’s actions were necessary or proportionate
(Damrosch, Henkin, Murphy, & Smit, 2009).
On the specic issue of imminence, the ICJ understood in
Gabckicovo that the temporal scope need not be materially
and temporally immediate but rather proximate or objectively
foreseeable (ICJ, 1997). As the ILC noted, the clear
establishment of the objective existence of the peril based
on reasonably available evidence at the time of the infringing
measure is enough to open the way for the claim of necessity
(ILC, 2001).
As is evident, the analytical framework of the factual test
needed to ascertain the validity of the claim of necessity is
actually fairly stringent, albeit highly context-
dependent. The best proof of the exceptional
nature of this justification is to be found
precisely in its application by the international
judiciary and arbitral tribunals. As noted by the
Commission in its 14th commentary to article
25 there is ample evidence of the claim of
necessity being submitted to international
tribunals in order to elude responsibility (ILC,
2001) and, consequently, a display by those
many judicial and arbitral instances of a very
rigorous scrutiny of the factual underpinnings
that uphold the validity of the claim (Paliouras,
2016).
The ICJ -again in the Gabcikovo-
Nagymaros Project case- provided useful
theoretical insights in order to check whether
the plea of necessity (as codied by the ILC)
could apply to any given situation. It wrote:
In the present case, the following basic
conditions (...) are relevant: it must have been
occasioned by an “essential interest” of the
State which is the author of the act conicting
with one of its international obligations; that
interest must have been threatened by a
“grave and imminent peril”; the act being
challenged must have been the “only means”
of safeguarding that interest; that act must not
have “seriously impair[ed] an essential interest”
of the State towards which the obligation
existed; and the State which is the author
of that act must not have “contributed to the
occurrence of the state of necessity. Those
conditions reect customary international law
(ICJ, 1997, paras. 51-52).
If with the enunciation put forth by the
ILC, the Court seems to develop pretty much
the same standards in a more articulated
and demanding way. The requisites for the
claim of necessity to hold, according to the
Gabcikovo bench are (1) the threat or harm
to an essential interest of the State, (2) the
existence of grave and imminent peril, (3) the
lack of less harmful alternatives, (4) the lack
of prejudice or harm to the essential interests
of the State to which the original obligation
was owed, and (5) the lack of contribution to
the peril by the claimant of necessity. These,
(19) It would be intellectually dishonest, however, to simply lump both sets of requisites together without disclaiming that the threshold
for the application of UNC article 51 is the occurrence of an armed attack by another State, which is exactly the very requisite that
this piece seeks to elude to avert the defenselessness of the attacked State when the author of the attack is a NSA.
28 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
do not diverge greatly from the ones included in article 25 of the
DARSIWA except for the lack of a less damaging option. In this
context, the di󰀨erence does not warrant too much explanation
because if there were a less harmful option, then the claim of
necessity (be it under the DARSIWA or under the standard set
by the ICJ) would be precluded from operation because the
infringement was not really necessary. As noted by the ILC,
the course of action taken must be the only way available to
safeguard the imperiled interest. The plea of necessity would
then be excluded if there are other legal means available, even
if they may be more costly or less convenient as long as they
are lawful (ILC, 2001).
3.2. The compatibility of article 25 of the DARSIWA with
the UN Charter’s article 51
Article 55 of the DARSIWA is clear in indicating that the
articles exist without prejudice to special regimes and become
inapplicable in the face of lex specialis. The ICJ has upheld
this maxim in both the Tehran Hostages case in regards to
diplomatic law and in the Gabcikovo-Nagymaros Project case
vis à vis treaty law. Article 25 of the DARSIWA itself curtly
states that “necessity cannot be invoked if the primary rules
exclude the possibility of invoking necessity. The latter, of
course, is not the case here. Even if article 51 UNC restricts
self-defense to armed exchanges between States, there is no
explicit exclusion of the invocation of the state of necessity. In
fact, necessity is contained within the very terms of reference
that States claim before the Council in exercising their right
of self-defense.
Rules of conict like article 55 DARSIWA only become
applicable when there is a conict of norms. Namely, when
the content and purpose of rules is contradictory or would lead
to opposing results. That is far from the case with the state of
necessity and the Charter norms on self-defense. Since one
looks at the responsibility of State in safeguarding essential
interests, and the other caters to the admissibility of actions
which would prima facie constitute a breach of interstate peace
and security (and thus, legality), there is no conict evident
between the purposes and texts of the norms.
In support of this, the so-called ‘Vienna rules’ (Bjorge,
2018) contained in articles 31-33 of the Vienna Convention
on the Law of Treaties allow for the harmonized interpretation
of “any relevant rules of international law applicable in the
relations between the parties” in article 31(3)(c). Hence, the
application of article 51 UNC need not exclude (nor should it)
the invocation of necessity under the terms of the DARSIWA
since they’re not incompatible and the former does not explicitly
exclude the latter.
Even more so, the welcoming of the state of necessity
into the fold of Charter-governed self-defense via the
UNSC would cater to an actual need of the international
community by bridging the gap created by
the exclusive interstate nature of article 51
UNC and allowing for self-defense against
NSAs under the watchful eye of the Council,
which can then ensure both the conformity
with international peace and security and,
by way of consequence, with the jus ad
bellum.
In this same train of thought and to quote
Schachter referring to the potential expansion
of article 51 of the UNC, it is true that States
exhibit signicant reluctance to “approve uses
of force under expanded conceptions of self-
defense (). Such reluctance is evidence of
a widespread perception that widening the
scope of self-defense will erode the basic
rule against the unilateral recourse to force”
(Schachter, 1991, p. 171). However, and as
pointed out several times in this piece, the
alternative to expanded interpretations or
lateral solutions (like the state of necessity)
does not in and of itself threaten to erode the
prohibition against the use of force, but rather
to update it to modern needs arising out of the
ever-changing nature of conict.
To avoid the risks highlighted by
Schachter, the responsibility of scrutinizing
the validity of the claim of the state of
necessity as a stand-in for self-defense in
the case where authorship of the attack
rests on a NSA in the territory of a non-
consenting third State should be entrusted
to institutions capable of answering in real
time (or as close as possible to) and which
have the authority to produce qualications
on the legality and legitimacy of a given
use of the plea of necessity. The rst of
these requirements is a direct function of
the immediacy built into the attack itself and
the need for defense without delay, which is
hardly accommodating with the parsimonious
times the international judiciary takes in
adjudicating claims. The second requirement
proposed goes to the need for a body
capable of simultaneously analyzing both the
legal and political dimensions of the actions
taken when the attack and the response
present themselves. It is for this reasons that
this paper suggest that no better alternative
may be found throughout international law
than the United Nations Security Council.
IUS ET VERITAS 63
29
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
4. Operationalizing the state of
necessity as an analogue of article
51 of the UN Charter
Arguably, the main aim of the UN Charter was to establish
“an institutional framework regulating the use of force by
substituting unilateral uses of force with collective ones when
certain situations of necessity, as dened by the system, arise”
(Tsagourias, 2011). But, as noted earlier, the right of self-defense
was left explicit in the text of the agreement in recognition of the
fundamental importance attached to the ability of the State to
preserve itself (Waltz, 1959). However, and as shown above,
this conventional iteration of the right of self-defense was built
on the notion that the only legally relevant uses of forces would
be those conducted between States.
This is perhaps the reason why Tsagourias argues that “[w]
hen a state for examples uses force in self-defense, it asserts a
right; it does not need to invoke necessity in order to justify its
right of self-defense as such” (2011, p. 29) without pondering
that the right of self-defense as enshrined in art. 51 UNC only
covers interstate uses of force and condemns to illegality those
not encompassed under the three exceptions to the prohibition
of article 2(4). Since self-defense against NSAs in the territory of
a third non-consenting State is not included in the exceptions to
the prohibition on the use of force, then it becomes necessary
to nd a legal path to safeguard the essential interest of the
attacked State.
The state of necessity could constitute the legal foothold
necessary to allow for such exercises of self-defense if the
requisites laid out in article 25 of the DARSIWA are met (which
would not be terribly di󰀩cult, as incidents like the Caroline or
Gorostiza have shown).
However, the typical processes associated with adjudication
of responsibility such as bilateral claims commissions or
recourse to judicial or arbitral settlement would belie the
imminence of the situation that triggers the illegality, and thus
condemn the claim to epiphenomenalit y. In this context, the rst
argument for proposing the UNSC as an ideal venue for airing
such claims is one of e󰀩ciency: The reporting duties stemming
from article 51 UNC and State practice provide the perfect
vehicle for alerting the Council when force is used against an
NSA in the territory of a third State that has not consented such
an action (regardless of its position vis à vis the NSA). The
best proof of this is that States are already doing it even if the
legality of the use of force is still up for debate, as the recent
Arria Formula Meeting of February showed.
There are many counters to the argument of using the UNSC
as an ideal venue for the examination of whether necessity
justies the attack against the territorial integrity and sovereignty
of the territorial State from which the NSA operates. Kelsen points
out the root of the most prevalent ones by
noting that the UNSC’s role “is not to maintain
or restore the law, but to maintain or restore
peace, which is not necessarily identical with
the law” (Kelsen, 1950, p. 294). Tsagourias
follows him in pointing out that the measures
adopted by the UNSC “can be coercive or
non-coercive, but they are not equivalent to
legal consequences as in the law of state
responsibility” (Tsagourias, 2011, p. 30).
Thus, the most pervasive arguments against
the idea of this paper lie within the realm of
the ‘political character’ of the decisions of the
UNSC. These will be addressed by o󰀨ering one
simple rebuttal: politics -such as those of the
UNSC- don’t exist in a vacuum, much less so
in international law where all ability is derived
from State concession. Even while being
preeminently political in its’ daily operation, the
Council is bound by international law and its
par excellence a venue where the currency is
law (even if it serves as a dressage for politics)
(Johnstone, 2003). The Council constantly
makes legal, and it seems a disservice to
articially separate ‘peace and security’ from
‘rule of law’.
In those few instances where the Council
has in fact reprimanded uses of force for being
aggressive, such as the Israeli bombing of
the Osirak reactor, its answers are deeply
embedded in legal terms and cause legal
consequences. In the majority of cases
where it has been silent, its inaction cannot
and should not be equated with tolerance or
legality (that is precisely where its political
nature shows itself). It is this very uidity that
has enabled the Council to procure a measure
of success in its task, but it by no means
signies that it is precluded from carrying out
legal analyses and assigning consequences
to illegal conducts. In short, politics and law
can and do mix, even if they mostly don’t at
the seat of the Council, which by no means
entail that they can’t. As an example of
this, note how the Council has the power to
qualify a use of force as aggressive under the
terms of the UN Charter and aided -among
others- by the denition of aggression. Is
that not, perchance, a most pure form of
legal determination of responsibility as a
consequence of a juridical qualication of any
given action?
30 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
4.1. The role of the UNSC in qualifying the validity of the
exception
If then, the claim of state of necessity is legally feasible in
order to exempt a State from responsibility when it conducts
attacks against a NSA in the territory of a non-consenting
third State, the next pressing question is about the logistics
of such a claim: would the UNSC be legally competent to
determine the existence and validity of the alleged state of
necessity plea?
The most tempting and straight-forward answer would be
that the State who has su󰀨ered the injury to its sovereignty
and territorial integrity (assuming it is an unwilling host of the
NSA and that it refuses to invite the originally attacked State
to intervene on its behalf) should have recourse to judicial
settlement as stated in article 33 of the UNC. However, if viewed
from the perspective of the State su󰀨ering the attack carried
out by the NSA, this makes little sense both in temporal and
logistical terms. Firstly, it would lack jus standi to make any
claims (not being the aggravated party on account of being
unable to show harm caused by another State); secondly,
the institution of proceedings before international tribunals is
anything but expedite (which would then render pointless the
situation of urgency and imminence of the attack), and lastly, it
completely ignores the likely reticence of the defending State to
have its actions submitted to judicial scrutiny (Gomez & Montiel,
2021). Without prejudice to the submission of the case to the
international judiciary once the dust has settled, there is another
instance that o󰀨ers a much faster and equally legal setting to
analyze the potential claim of necessity in using force against
the territorial integrity of the third State: The United Nations
Security Council.
In its Nicaragua ruling, the ICJ a󰀩rmed without controversy
that any measures taken under article 51 must be immediately
reported to the Council (ICJ, 1986) and that it is tasked with
determining the conformity of the instance of self-defense
with the law governing the use of force between States. The
same is stated by article 51 ejusdem in its second sentence.
However, as noted at the outset of this work, the exercise of
self-defense against NSAs (as di󰀨erentiated from interstate use
of force) seems to be outside of the scope of activity of article
51 (hence the need to have recourse to the law governing
State responsibility). The reason for this is that NSAs are not
States and therefore any armed attack would fail, by reason
of its authorship, to meet the threshold required by article 51
(Gill & Tibori-Szabó, 2019) which would therefore theoretically
negate any obligation of reporting to the Council on the part of
the defending State.
However, this interpretive syllogism is not entirely faithful
to the truth of State practice. As Lewis, Modirzadeh, and Blum
have identied, there is ample practice in the context of the
UNSC of informing the Council when measures are carried out
under self-defense against non-state actors to
the tune of some 118 instances since the year
of 1951 and until 2018 which have involved
instances of self-defense against NSAs or
States and NSAs jointly (Lewis, Modirzadeh,
& Blum, 2019). This has become especially
recurrent in the context of the invasions of
Iraq and Afghanistan in the early 2000’s and
later on with the measures taken to combat
the so-called Islamic State of Syria and the
Levant (ISIL/Daesh), it is also a constant for
Israel as a function of its refusal to recognize
Palestine as a State and thereby treating its
government as an NSA.
It could then be argued at face value,
and pending a conscientious review of
concurrence of State practice and opinio
juris, that a customary obligation may exist
or is -at the very least- in formative period,
which extends the duty of reporting measures
taken under article 51 even if the target is
not directly another State (with the ensuing
vicious circle question of whether it really is an
article 51 report or something else). As pointed
out by the ILC, the practice of International
Organizations and of member States within
them can -in principle- constitute acceptable
practice in determining the existence of
rules of customary law (ILC, 2018). This is
further supported by the near-monopoly the
UNSC holds over international peace and
security and its ‘primary’ responsibility in the
maintenance of it. As a consequence, even if
it is not mandatory, the practice of reporting
instances of self-defense to the Council
should be analyzed from the lens of material
reality and the primacy of State practice, as
observed by the ICJ in the Continental Shelf
case concerning Libya and Malta (ICJ, 1985).
From this it follows that States can notify the
Council (even if they’re not explicitly obligated
to) of any measures taken under the aegis of
self-defense against NSAs in the territory of
a third non-consenting State.
If they can do so in respect of article
51 measures, would itnot be the same hold
largely true if the allegation were not one of
self-defense but of a permissible violation
of article 2(4) UNC excused by the state of
necessity in the supra referenced terms? The
argument here is that they are in fact allowed
to do so as a function of identity in nature
IUS ET VERITAS 63
31
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
and purpose of the claim in a teleological reading. As noted
earlier, article 51 is an exception (inherent and inalienable as
it may be, but exceptional nevertheless) to the prohibition on
the use of force against the territorial integrity and political
independence of the aggravated State, therefore, the legal
usefulness of claiming self-defense is to exclude the possibility
of labelling the measures as incurring in the use of aggressive
force. The same rationale applies for claiming the existence
of a state of necessity to justify the adoption of measures that
would otherwise violate article 2(4) UNC.
The e󰀨ect of the validity of such a claim is precisely the
erosion of unlawfulness of the action, in the intelligence that the
preservation of essential interests of the State is at play here
and thus warrants the commission of a prima facie unlawful act.
The conclusion is that it would be arbitrary and senseless to
distinguish between a claim of force being used in self-defense
under article 51 UNC and one of state of necessity made under
article 25 of the ILC’s DARSIWA since these two are motivated
by almost identical circumstances (armed attack by another
State and armed attack by a NSA), seek to safeguard the same
essential interests (even if the threshold required by article 51
UNC is lower in that any armed attack by another State warrants
self-defense and the claim of state of necessity would require
demonstration of the specic essential interest in jeopardy),
and have the same e󰀨ect (exempting the classication of the
measures taken as violations of article 2(4) UNC).
Thus far, it is evident that States can report to the UNSC
the measures adopted against the armed attack carried out by
an NSA justied under a state of necessity, because they do. It
has also been shown that the Council is competent to receive
such a notication since the activity falls squarely under the
category of ‘international peace and security, but then the most
important question arises: does the UNSC possess the power
to qualify the validity and legality of such actions?
Even with respect of de jure article 51 communications, the
Council rarely responds o󰀩cially to self-defense notications.
Bearing in mind that if the UNSC reaches the conclusion that
a particular instance of self-defense fails to conform to the
parameters emanating from article 51, the forcible conclusion
would be that such an action constitutes a breach of article
2(4) UNC. However, nowhere in the law are declarations of
responsibility automatic or self-executing, and the law governing
the use of force is no exception. In this context, the UNSC
would have to formally declare the existence of a breach of
international peace and security as indicated by article 39
UNC and then proceed to declare responsibilities and/or award
reparations. Nevertheless, this is seldom the case with the
UNSC. In most instances, the Council opts for silence, in some
other select ones it has chosen non-condemnatory language
ordering the re-establishment of the previous status quo, and
only exceptionally has it outright qualied an action carried out
under the shadow of article 51 UNC as illegal.
As noted by Sievers and Dawn this variable
practice pursuant to article 51 is compounded
by the fact that the UNSC typically avoids
determinations as to the self-defense nature
of an action reported to it (Sievers & Daws,
2014). However, the fact that it doesn’t qualify
does not entail (by and large) that it can’t.
The practice of the UNSC in dealing with
communications concerning self-defense has
been mostly of silence (Lewis, Modirzadeh,
& Blum, 2019), with the notable exception
of S/RES/487 (1981) dealing with the Israeli
preventive strike against the Osirak reactor in
Iraq and a handful of others. Thus, it is safe to
conclude that the Council rarely qualies the
legality of allegations of self-defense (Kerr,
2012). This silence can be read in several
ways. On the one hand, given its mandate
to monitor and uphold international peace
and security, the silence of the Council when
presented with an article 51 communication
can be read as a conclusion of lawfulness
(Quigley, 2003) much in the same logic that
silence creates acquiescence under certain
circumstances. It has also been posited
that silence can amount to mere toleration
without necessarily conveying acceptance
or lawfulness (Orakhelashvili, 2015), or
alternatively one could argue that no legally
relevant e󰀨ect should be deduced from the
inaction of the Council (Montiel, 2021) as “a
handful of States cannot speak for all States,
and it is improper to infer agreement from
silence“ (Glennon, 2001, p. 75). Regardless
of this, article 51 UNC calls for an ex post
control of the conformity of the measures
adopted by the defending State and it is
patent that the Council can and should answer
as a matter of law. This is the exact same
holding of the ICJ in its Nicaragua ruling,
later upheld in the Oil Platforms Case (ICJ,
2003), in which the Court found the UNSC to
be competent to determine lawfulness of the
whose justication is sought on the basis of
self-defense. In this intelligence, the answer
is almost obvious, even if the Council is not
a judicial organ, it is required by the Charter
to analyze the conformity of any action taken
under article 51 UNC with the law governing
self-defense and use of force in general.
More to the point, if the Council is tasked
32 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
(20) Also note how the Council occasionally dabbles in quasi-judicial exercises with the Al-Qaeda Sanctions Committee and in would-
be normative practices when it issues thematic resolutions like s/res/1882 (2009), none of which have been met with protest from
Member States, which would then o󰀨er the reasonable assumption that such a behavior from the Council is -at least- not ultra vires.
with receiving article 51 UNC communications and qualifying
the legality of the use of force therein exerted, possesses the
competence to declare the existence of a breach of international
peace and security, and has the primary responsibility for the
maintenance of international peace and security as per article
24 of the UNC, alongside with the power to adopt any decisions
it deems necessary for the restoration of international peace
and security (such as declaring the illegality of any given use of
force), then the doctrine of implied powers as put forth by the ICJ
in its Advisory Opinion concerning Reparations for Damages
Suered in the Service of the United Nations (ICJ, 1949) would
force the conclusion that the Council needs to have such a
power in order to carry out its responsibilities e󰀨ectively(20).
Nevertheless, authors such as Klabbers have argued
against such a notion claiming that the UNSC is inherently
political in nature and should not be deemed to have the
power to determine juridical situations (Klabbers, 2015). This
conclusion seems to run counter to the bona de interpretation
of the UN Charter and the relevant dicta of the ICJ concerning
the law governing the use of force. The fact that it is a political
body in nature need not necessarily compromise the legitimacy
of juridical determinations the Council may reach in qualifying
the legality of self-defense, it may even enrich it by virtue of ‘the
power of the better argument’ (Johnstone, 2003) and because
the of political counter-weights present in the Council under the
guise of technical arguments based in the law.
This goes to show that the Council can in fact determine the
legality of measures taken under article 51 UNC. If the same test
of identity applied a few paragraphs ago is applied here, there is
no reason why the Council would be precluded from entertaining
a debate on the legality of measures adopted against an armed
attack of a NSA justied in a state of necessity. It would, after
all, be an act susceptible of constituting breach of article 2(4)
of the UNC and would therefore merit the Councils attention
with a view to determining whether or not such use of force is
aggressive. This in turn, falls under the purview of the Council
without the need of any further analysis.
Solid evidence for this possibility, is provided by article 2 of
A/RES/3314 (XXIX) which states that “the Security Council may,
in conformity with the Charter, conclude that a determination
that an act of aggression has been committed would not be
justied in the light of other relevant circumstances”. While
the cited text is in the negative, it does reveal that the Council
may look to external circumstances (such as the existence
of a state of necessity) in determining whether a given use
of force constitutes an act of aggression under article 2(4) of
the UNC. In fact, it is this same article 2 of
the denition of aggression resolution of the
General Assembly that utilizes the language
of justication to preclude illegality (bearing in
mind that aggression is clearly illegal under
Charter law and a breach of a myriad of
international obligations), and thus signals to
the compatibility of the regime of excuses in
analyzing uses of force as per the DARSIWA.
Nor does it warrant further scrutiny the
question of whether the Council may analyze
the validity of the claimed state of necessity
on the part of a State countering an attack by
an NSA. The UNSC has no xed parameters
(other than necessity and proportionality) to
determine whether the use of force in self-
defense is legal or not, but can -and always
does- look to the UN Charter, and general
international law for guidance. In this context,
it is especially noteworthy that necessity is
already built into the criteria for assessing
the legality of measures adopted in self-
defense, as was held by the World Court in
the Oil Platforms case (ICJ, 1986), what the
here proposed solution would entail is merely
providing a more structured scrutiny of the
necessity requirement in order to preclude
the wrongfulness of the use of force against
the territory from where the NSA operates.
The notion entertained here is, of
course, one concerned with possibility and
competence of the Council. A di󰀨erent one
-and perhaps more pressing- is whether the
Council (and the member States of the UN)
will entertain such claims. The answer to such
a question would necessitate member States
bringing the claim forth and seeing if, in being
demanded a determination, it will oblige.
There is nothing to suggest that the practice
of the UNSC wouldn’t evolve to meet such
requirements if pressed to by the membership
of the Organization in the search for a viable
alternative to being fated to su󰀨er damage as
a consequence the unwillingness or inability
to foresee this modality of violence back when
the UNC was being drafted.
IUS ET VERITAS 63
33
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
5. Conclusions
As reality has shown, the particular mode of political violence
that occurs when NSAs use the territory of a third State (with or
without its toleration) to launch armed attacks against another
State is not a new phenomenon and is, presumably, here to
stay. An international law which fates the attacked State to such
su󰀨ering is not one particularly coherent with the principle of
sovereign equality and also one that fails to recognize that the
State, and its sacred duty to protect its territory and people,
are at the center of the normative order. Therefore, it stands to
reason that the law would -by omission or lack of foresight- bind
States to su󰀨er such attacks without remedy.
This article has shown that, unless clear indicated
otherwise, the law governing the responsibility of the State for
internationally wrongful acts is applicable to the rules governing
self-defense (in the context of the use of force regime) when
the author of the attack is not a State but an NSA. Additionally,
the identity in object and purpose (and requisites of operation)
of both regimes would render arbitrary any attempt to bar the
application of the state of necessity to the situation where an
NSA attacks a State from the territory of a third State that fails
to honor its duty to prevent damage from its territory to the
defending State.
The realization that -although theoretically constrained by
the interstate dynamics of the UN Charter- the UNSC has near-
absolute monopoly on the scrutiny of the use of force by States
should caution that attempting to divert such a competence is
an exercise in wishful thinking. The powers and attributions of
the Council have grown over the years because the realities of
politics and law have demanded it (and because States rarely
protest the decisions of the Council because it acts on delegated
authority from all the members of the UN). After all, the Council
is little more than the voice of its members (Hurd, 2018) and
its politicized application of the law is -to the chagrin of many
observers- an inescapable feature of the use of force system.
In this context, the argument against allowing the Council to
examine the claim of necessity when defending against the
attack of an NSA from the territory of a third non-consenting
State on the grounds of its political nature would certainly raise
questions as to why such an examination is not questioned when
the participants of the exchange of violence are only States.
As annotated above, Schachter (1991) cautioned against
licentious interpretations of self-defense that could have the e󰀨ect
of eroding the prohibition on the use of force, in the way that
doctrines like the ‘unwilling or unable’ do. Arguably, this concern
reects the need for strict rules that are not easy to bypass via
semantic sleight of hand on the part of war-prone States. The
proposition of this paper seeks to uphold the spirit of Schachter’s
advice. In importing the rules governing the plea of necessity
and incorporating them into the analytical toolkit of the UNSC,
far from attempting to erode the prohibition
against the use of force, the aim is to strengthen
it and to update it so that it may better serve
its real purpose: guaranteeing international
peace and security in a way that is respectful
of the sovereignty of all States involved without
imposing undue burdens upon them. The idea
is to use already existing law to ll the lacunae
that may be lled, as is the case here.
In a system, such as international
law, which has its origin in the freedom of
States there is a severe di󰀨erence between
self-limitation in the interest of peaceful
coexistence and a shackle impeding the
defense of the population and territory of the
States themselves on account of a normative
oversight of seven decades ago. The claim of
the plea of necessity arbitered by the UNSC
is a legally coherent attempt to turn the latter
into the former in a way that is respectful
of existing law and cautiously deferential to
national sovereignties.
Bibliographic references
Ago, R. (1980). Addendum to the Eight Report on
State Responsibility, UN Doc. A/CN.4/318/ADD.5-
7. Yearbook of the International Law Commission.
Akande, D. & Liefländer, T. (2013). Clarifying
Necessity, Imminence, and Proportionality in
the Law of Self-Defense. American Journal of
Intenrational Law, 107, 563-570.
Arimatsu, L. & Schmitt, M. (2021). The Plea of
Necessity: an oft overlooked response option
to hostile cyber obperations. International Law
Studies, 1172-1198.
Bethlehem, D. (2012). Self-Defense Against an
Imminent or Actual Armed Attack by Nonstate
Actors. American Journal of International Law,
106, 769-773.
Bethlehem, D. (2021). Self-Defense against an
imminent or actual armed attack by nonstate
actors. American Journal of International Law,
106, 770-771.
Bjorge, E. (2018). The Vienna Rules, Evolutionary
Interpretation, and the Intentions of Parties. In A.
Bianchi, D. Peat & M. Windsor, Interpretation in
International Law (pp. 189-203). Oxford University
Press.
Boed, R. (2000). State of Necessity as a Justication
for Internationally Wrongful Conduct. Yale Human
Rights and Development Law Journal, 3(1), 1- 44.
34 IUS ET VERITAS 63
Moisés Montiel Mogollón
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
Britannica, E. (2021, August 14). Dumbarton Oaks Conference.
Encyclopaedia Britannica. https://www.britannica.com/event/
Dumbarton-Oaks-Conference
Chachko, E. & Deeks, A. (2016, October 10). Which States Support the
‘Unwilling and Unable’ Test?. Lawfare Blog. https://www.lawfareblog.
com/which-states-support-unwilling-and-unable-test#UnitedStates
Cheng, B. (2006). General Principles of Law as Applied by International
Courts and Tribunals. University College London.
Crawford, J. (2019). Brownlie’s Principles of International Law (9th
edition). Oxford University Press.
Damrosch, L., Henkin, L., Murphy, S. & Smit, H. (2009). International
Law. Cases and Materials (5th edition). St. Paul: West.
DeLaurentis, J. (2021, March 16). Letter dated 8 March 2021 from
the Permanent Representative of Mexico to the United Nations
addressed to the Secretary-General and the President of the
Security Council. United Nations Digital Archive. https://documents-
dds-ny.un.org/doc/UNDOC/GEN/N21/066/46/PDF/N2106646.
pdf?OpenElement
De la Fuente, J. (2021, February 24). Letter dated 8 March 2021
from the Permanent Representative of Mexico to the United Nations
addressed to the Secretary-General and the President of the
Security Council. United Nations Digital Archive. https://documents-
dds-ny.un.org/doc/UNDOC/GEN/N21/066/46/PDF/N2106646.
pdf?OpenElement
Dobos, N. (2011). Insurrection and Intervention: The two faces of
sovereignty. University Press.
Drnas de Clément, Z. (2002). Las normas imperativas de Derecho
Internacional general (jus cogens). Dimensión sustancial. In Z.
Drnas de Clément, & M. Lerner, Estudios de derecho internacional
en homenaje al profesor Ernesto J. Rey Caro (pp. 647-680). Marcos
Lerner Editora.
Fenwick, C. (1965). International Law (4th ed.). Appleton-Century-
Crofts.
Franck, T. (1970). Who Killed Article 2(4)? or: Changing Norms
Governing the Use of Force by States. American Journal of International
Law, 80 9 - 837.
Gill, T. & Tibori-Szabó, K. (2019). Twelve Key Questions on Self-
defense Against Non-State Actors. International Law Studies, 468-503.
Glennon, M. (2001). Limits of Law, Prerogatives of Power: Interventionism
After Kosovo. Palgrave MacMillan.
Gomez, S. & Montiel, M. (2021, February 19). A Commentary on the
Arbitral Award of 3 October, 1899 (Guyana v. Venezuela) jurisdiction
ruling: The road to hell is paved with good intentions. Opinio Juris. http://
opiniojuris.org/2021/02/19/a-commentary-on-the-arbitral-award-of-3-
october-1899-guyana-v-venezuela-jurisdiction-ruling-the-road-to-hell-
is-paved-with-good-intentions/
Gurmendi, A. (2020, February 17). The Other Carolines. Opinio Juris.
http://opiniojuris.org/2020/02/17/the-other-carolines/
Haque, A. (2021, March 24). Self-Defense Against Non-State Actors:
All Over the Map. Just Security. https://www.justsecurity.org/75487/
self-defense-against-non-state-actors-all-over-the-map/
Heller, K. (2019, March 19). The Earliest Invocation
of “Unwilling or Unable”. Opinio Juris. http://
opiniojuris.org/2019/03/19/the-earliest-invocation-
of-unwilling-or-unable/
Hershey, A. (1927). The Essentials of International
Public Law and Organization (revised edition). The
Macmillan Company.
ILC. (2001). Draft Articles on Responsibility of
States for Internationally Wrongful Acts with
Commentaries. Yearbook of the International Law
Commission (pp. 1-143). United Nations.
ILC. (2018). Draft Conclusions on Identication of
Customary International Law, with commentaries.
Yearbook of the International Law Commission.
International Court of Justice. (1949, April 11).
Advisory Opinion concerning Reparation for Injuries
Suered in the Service of the United Nations. ICJ
Reports.
International Court of Justice. (1949, April 9). Corfu
Channel Case (United Kingdom v. Albania). ICJ
Reports.
International Court of Justice. (1986, June 27).
Case Concerning Military and Paramilitary
Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v.
United States of America. ICJ Reports.
International Court of Justice. (1997, September
25). Gabcikovo-Nagymaros Project Case (Hungary
v. Slovakia). ICJ Reports.
International Court of Justice. (2003, November 6).
Case Concerning Oil Platforms (Islamic Republic
of Iran v. United States of America). ICJ Reports.
International Court of Justice. (2004, July 9).
Advisory Opinion concerning Legal Consequences
of the Construction of a Wall in the Occupied
Palestinian Territories. ICJ Reports.
International Court of Justice. (2005, December 19).
Case Concerning Armed Activities on the Territory
of the Congo (Democratic Republic of the Congo v.
Rwanda). ICJ Reports.
International Law Commission. (2019). Fourth report
on peremptory norms of general international law
(jus cogens). 71st Session (pp. 1-70). United Nations.
Jellinek, G. (1880). Die Rechtliche Natur der
Staaten-vertrage. A. Holder.
Johnstone, I. (2003). Security Council Deliberations:
The Power of the Better Argument. European
Journal of International Law, 437-480.
Kelsen, H. (1950). The law of the United Nations.
Steven & Sons.
Keohane, R., & Nye, J. (2000). Globalization:
What’s New? What’s Not? (And so What?). Foreign
Policy, 118), 104 -119.
IUS ET VERITAS 63
35
The Plea of State of Necessity: A palatable normative framework for extraterritorial self-defense
against Non-State Actors
El Alegato de Estado de Necesidad: Un marco jurídico digerible para la legítima defensa
extraterritorial contra Actores No Estatales
Revista IUS ET VERITAS Nº 63, diciembre 2021 / ISSN 1995-2929 (impreso) / ISSN 2411-8834 (en línea)
Kerr, O. (2012). A Theory of Law. Green Bag, 1.
Klabbers, J. (2015). Intervention, Armed
Intervention, Armed Attack, Threat to Peace, Act
of Aggression, and Threat or Use of Force: Whats
the Di󰀨erence? In M. Wellers, Oxford Handbook
of the Use of Force in International Law. Oxford
University Press.
Kotlik, M. (2017). Defying the Theoretical
Constraints of State-Centric Approaches: A Review
of Non-State Actors in International Law. Israel Law
Review, 87-105.
Kretzmer, D. (2013). The Inherent Right to Self-
Defence and Proportionality in Jus Ad Bellum.
European Journal of International Law, 24(1),
235-282.
Lewis, D., Modirzadeh, N, & Blum, G. (2019).
Quantum of Silence: Inaction and Jus ad Bellum.
Harvard Law School Program on International Law
and Armed Conict, 1-79.
Modirzadeh, N. (2021). Statement of Professor
Naz Modirzadeh to the UN Security Council on
February 24, 2021. Arria-Formula Meeting of the
Security Council on the theme “Upholding the
collective security system of the Charter of the
United Nations: the use of force in international
law, non-State actors and legitimate self-defence”
(pp. 3-9). United Nations.
Montiel, M. (2021). The Consent-Based Problems
Surrounding the Doctrine of the Persistent
Objector. Michigan Journal of International Law.
Forthcoming.
Montiel, M. (2021, June 23). Fantastical Opinio Juris
and How to Find It. Opinio Juris. http://opiniojuris.
org/2021/06/23/fantastical-opinio-juris-and-how-
to-nd-it/
O’Connell, M. (2019, March 8). Settling the India-
Pakistan Impasse … At Last. EJIL: Talk!: https://
www.ejiltalk.org/settling-the-india-pakistan-
impasse-at-last/
Orakhelashvili, A. (2015). Changing Jus Cogens
Through State Practice? The Case of the Prohibition
of the Use of Force and its Exceptions. In M. Weller,
The Oxford Handbook of the Use of Force in
International Law. Oxford University Press.
Paddeu, F. (2020, August 7). Military Assistance on Request and
General Reasons Against Force: Consent as a justication for the use
of foce. Legal Studies Research Paper Series(28/2020), 1-47.
Paliouras, V. (2016). State of Necessity and Sovereign Insolvency. In A.
Segura, The Reform of International Economic Governance. Routledge.
Permanent Court of International Justice. (1927, September 7). Case
of the SS Lotus (France v. Turkey). PCIJ Series A, No. 10.
Quigley, J. (2003). The Afghanistan War and Self-Defense. Valparaiso
University Law Review.
Rodick, B. (1928). The Doctrine of Necessity in International Law.
Columbia University Press.
Schachter, O. (1991). International Law in Theory and in Practice. Brill.
Sharma, Y. & Agarwal, P. (2020, May 9). Dealing With Non-State
Actors In International Law: The “Unwilling And Unable Doctrine”.
The Fletcher Forum of World A󰀨airs. http://www.etcherforum.org/
the-rostrum/2020/5/9/dealing-with-non-state-actors-in-international-
law-the-unwilling-and-unable-doctrine
Sievers, L. & Daws, S. (2014). The Procedure of the UN Security
Council. Oxford University Press.
Taft, W. (2004). Self-Defense and the Oil Platforms Decision. Yale
Journal of International Law, 29, 295-306.
Tibori-Szabó, K. (2011). Anticipatory Action in Self-Defence: Essence
and Limits Under International Law. The Hague: TMC Asser Press.
Tladi, D. (2013). An Assessment of Bethlehem’s Principles on the Use
of Force Against Non-State Actors. American Journal of International
Law, 107, 570-575.
Torp, S. (2014). The prohibition of the use of force as jus cogens:
Explaining apparent derogations. Netherlands International Law
Review, 167-193.
Tsagourias, N. (2011). Necessity and the Use of Force: A Special
Regime. Netherland Yearbook of International Law, 11- 42.
United Nations. (1945). United Nations Charter. United Nations.
United Nations. (1974). A/RES/3314 (XXIX). United Nations.
Waltz, K. (1959). Man, The State, and War. New Columbia.
Williams, G. (2013). Piercing the Shield of Sovereignty: An Assessment
of the Legal Status of the ‘Unwilling or Unable’ Test. UNSW Law
Journal, 36, 619 - 6 41.
Ziccardi, G. (2007). Providing a Right of Self-Defense Against Large-
Scale Attacks by Irregular Forces: The Israeli-Hezbollah Conict.
Harvard International Law Journal, 101-112.